Symplectic categories

Alan Weinstein
2010 Portugaliae Mathematica  
Quantization problems suggest that the category of symplectic manifolds and symplectomorphisms be augmented by the inclusion of canonical relations as morphisms. These relations compose well when a transversality condition is satisfied, but the failure of the most general compositions to be smooth manifolds means that the canonical relations do not comprise the morphisms of a category. We discuss several existing and potential remedies to the nontransversality problem. Some of these involve
more » ... riction to classes of lagrangian submanifolds for which the transversality property automatically holds. Others involve allowing lagrangian "objects" more general than submanifolds. In his work on Fourier integral operators, Hörmander [12], following Maslov [15], observed that, under a transversality assumption, the set-theoretic composition of two canonical relations is again a canonical relation, and that this composition is a "classical limit" of the composition of certain operators. Shortly thereafter, Sniatycki and Tulczyjew [21] defined symplectic relations as isotropic 1 submanifolds of products and showed that this class of relations was closed under "clean" composition (see Section 2 below). They also observed that the natural relation between a symplectic manifold and the quotient of a submanifold by the kernel of the pulled-back symplectic form is a symplectic relation. Following in part some (unpublished) ideas of the author, Guillemin and Sternberg [9] observed that the linear canonical relations (i.e., lagrangian subspaces of products of symplectic vector spaces) could be considered as the morphisms of a category, and they constructed a partial quantization of this category (in which lagrangian subspaces are enhanced by halfdensities. The automorphism groups in this category are the linear symplectic groups, and the restriction of the Guillemin-Sternberg quantization to each such group is a metaplectic representation. On the other hand, the quantization of certain compositions of canonical relations leads to ill-defined operations at the quantum level, such as the evaluation of a delta "function" at its singular point, or the multiplication of delta functions. The quantization of the linear symplectic category was part of a larger project of quantizing canonical relations (enhanced with extra structure, such as half-densities) in a functorial way, and this program was set out more formally by the present author in [24] and [25]. It was advocated there that canonical relations should be considered as the morphisms of a "category", and that quantization should be a functor from there to a category of linear spaces and linear maps, consistent with some additional structures. The word "category" appears in quotation marks above because the composition of canonical relations can fail to be a canonical relation, as will be explained in detail below, so we do not have a category. Briefly, there are two problems.
doi:10.4171/pm/1866 fatcat:xod6v7hfvbdipfoplhrl4ys3li